• BEING AND NOTHINGNESS: AN ESSAY ON PHENOMENOLOGICAL ONTOLOGY (1943) BY JEAN-PAUL SARTRE
    04/ 01/ 2022
    Jean-Paul Sartre (1905-1980) was one of the representative philosophers of the 20th century. The development of Jean-Paul Sartre's philosophical thoughts can be divided into two stages. In the first stage, Sartre's philosophy mainly focused on the individual (l'individu), starting with The transcendence of Ego (1936). In the second stage, Sartre's philosophy goes from the individual to the social (le social), beginning with Notebooks for an Ethics/ Les cahiers pour une morale   (1946–7, first published in 1983). The work Being and Nothingness: An Essay On Phenomenological Ontology / L'Être et le Néant: Essai d'ontologie phénoménologique (1943) is the complete collection of Sartre's philosophical ideas at the first stage of his philosophical career. This is a colossal and incomprehensible work, so it is a huge challenge for many readers to grasp the contents of the book. Therefore, we are introducing the following article by Gary Cox, a contemporary philosopher who has a lot of research on Jean-Paul Sartre and existentialism, so that you can understand the main ideas of Being and Nothingness:   The original of Being and Nothingness (1943) published by Gallimard English translation by Hazel E. Barnes (1956) Sartre’s magnum opus, his major philosophical work. Although by no means his longest work, even at a length of over six hundred pages, it is by far his most important and influential. Most of the analysis of Sartre’s existentialism conducted by philosophers around the world has centered and continues to centre upon this work. No single book, perhaps, can lay claim to being the “bible” of existentialism, but Being and Nothingness is certainly one of the cornerstones of the existentialist school of thought. In its grand proportions and ambitions, in its structural and linguistic density and complexity, the work asprires to take its place alongside other epic, challenging, heavyweight texts of Continental philosophy, such as Heidegger’s Being and Time (1972), Schopenhauer’s World as Will and Representation (1818) or Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit (1807), works that in their different ways offer a comprehensive integrated, holistic account of the various essential features of the human condition. Sartre’s abiding question or concern in Being and Nothingness is more or less the same as that of his three major influences, Hegel, Husserl and Heidegger. What must be the nature of a being that has and is a relation-ship to the world, that is an awareness of the world and acts upon the world? Employing the dialectical style and method of his philosophical influences as an effective means of revealing the fundamental, internal relations existing between apparently distinct phenomena, Sartre argues that the only kind of being that can exist as a relation to reality or the world is a bring that is, in itself, nothing; a being that is a negation or a non-being. Some Sartre scholars argue that a more accurate English translation of L’Étre et le Néant, the French title of the work, would be Being and Non-being, but Being and Nothingness is now so well established as the work’s enigmatic sounding English title that it is unlikely any publisher would ever dare change it. It is certainly the complex dynamics of the relationship between being and non-being, or more accurately being-in-itself and being-for-itself as Sartre calls them, that is at the heart of Being and Nothingness. The work develops wide-ranging descriptions of both the relationship between being-for-itself and being-in-itself, and the relationship between one being-for-itself and another, descriptions that highlight seemingly endless implications and ramifications that extend to all aspects of a person’s being in the world - consciousness, temporality, embodiment, action, desire, freedom, anxiety, responsibility, bad faith, being-for-others, mortality and so on. It is the sheer saturation of Being and Nothingness with examples, illustrations, associations, insights, suggestions and pointers that most strongly reveals Sartre’s genius and makes his philosophy so interesting to study, criticize and develop. Precisely because Sartre strives at every turn to mention the diverse implications of his complex thought, the arguments in Being and Nothingness are somewhat convoluted and the progress of the work rather meandering. Sartre intends to leave no stone unturned, and to “get through” Being and Nothingness, or even significant parts of it, the reader must commit time and effort to taking a rambling but fascinating journey with Sartre as he maps out a vast and complex territory. The committed reader will eventually recognize that the book is relentless, even ruthless, in its pursuit of an overall direction and thesis, building up into an exhaustive, unified, brutally honest and largely coherent theory of human reality. Starting with an exploration of the ontology of being and non-being the book moves on to explain that consciousness is non-being as it is manifested at the level of phenomena or the phenomenological level. Consciousness is variously and painstakingly described as that which exists for itself rather than in itself (hence Sartre’s term “being-for-itself”), as a lack of being which strives in vain to achieve identity with itself by overcoming that lack, and as essentially intentional, temporal, embodied and free. Sartre’s radical freedom thesis derives directly from his philosophy of mind. Each person is a temporal flight from his present nothingness towards a future coincidence with himself that is never achieved. Each person is a futurizing intention, and it is in that open future that defines him and at which he aims that a person is free. As essentially free, people cannot not be free, they have to choose who they are and what they do and every attempt to evade this responsibility by choosing not to choose constitutes bad faith. A major theme of the book is how the key phenomena of consciousness, freedom and bad faith function in and are conditioned by relations with others. Sartre describes the fundamental ontological structures of the phenomenon of being-for-others before placing flesh on ontological bones through his intriguingly penetrating analysis of concrete relations with others. He brilliantly describes love, hate, sexual desire, masochism, sadism and indifference, explaining in a manner perfectly consistent with his overall thesis what is essential to them, how they arise out of the very nature of out being in the world and how they are intimately related to one another. Meanwhile, as he proceeds with his main agenda of analysing these concrete relations, he rewards his reader with a wealth of thought-provoking insights into the nature and significance of various other peculiarly Other-related phenomena such as nudity, obscenity, grace and humiliation. Though there is a lot in Being and Nothingness that demands criticism and clarification, Sartre’s piercing insight, his intellectual creativity, the extraordinary ability he demonstrates throughout the work to identify and describe the essential nature and connectedness of all aspects of the human condition, are remarkable and hugely inspiring.
  • ANTIGONE'S CLAIM BY JUDITH BUTLER
    27/ 12/ 2021
    Antigone’s Claim, whose subtitle is Kinship Between Life and Death, is a combination of the lectures of an American female philosopher Judith Butler at many prestigious universities such as California, Cornell and Princeton University. It is about Antigone by Sophocles, a deeply influential play in the history of Western philosophy. The birth of Antigone’s Claim has been such a significant event in American academic world for the past 20 years. Judith Butler's Antigone's Claim is an attempt to re-perceive the relationship between the family and the state through the figure of Antigone in ancient Greek tragedy, and from that to present a new way of reading this figure in the context of contemporary politics. In this work, Judith Butler reexamines the historical dominance of ideas raised by Hegel, Lacan and Irigaray on the issue of representativeness of Antigone. To Hegel, Antigone represents the kinship system in the field of family while Creon represents the political system in the field of society. The conflict between these two characters is an expression of the conflict between the family and the state, and according to Hegel's dialectic logic, this conflict will be reconciled in a way that the family will be ... dissipated in the state. Inheriting Hegel’s idea, Lacan put her into the Symbolic, the idealized realm of kinship which is separated from the social realm. Irigaray considered her as a representative of the transition from maternity to paternity through the symbol of “blood”. As a result of this reading, Antigone, in other words…..?, has no place in social life as a citizen. Butler argued that this was a misreading of Antigone, because as a political figure, she “points somewhere else, not to politics as a question of representation but to that political possibility that emerges when the limits to representation and representability are exposed.” (p.2) In protest of this reading, she reinterpreted the position “caught in a web of relations that produce no coherent position within kinship” (p.57), a web where “the terms of kinship become irreversibly equivocal” (p.57). Family is simultaneously Antigone's destiny and a collection of practices she performs. In that position, her actions led her to "repeat the deviation of a normal." In a social arrangement, everything is justified by norm, will deviations’ existence be justified or will they be extinguished in some way to ensure smooth operation of the normative system? Antigone's claim is the claim for the right to exist of those who are pushed to the course of fate as many other blessed people that hold standard positions. Her claim was nothing but the right to cry, but it was still something far away. The Vietnamese translation of this work is available at Ex Libris Hermes. Please drop by to pick it up.
  • GREAT BOOKS OF THE WESTERN WORLD 3
    20/ 12/ 2021
    Volume 31 René Descartes Rules for the Direction of the Mind Discourse on the Method Meditations on First Philosophy Objections Against the Meditations and Replies The Geometry Benedict de Spinoza Ethics Volume 32 John Milton English Minor Poems Paradise Lost Samson Agonistes Areopagitica Volume 33 Blaise Pascal The Provincial Letters Pensées Scientific and mathematical essays Volume 34 Sir Isaac Newton Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy Optics Christiaan Huygens Treatise on Light Volume 35 John Locke A Letter Concerning Toleration Concerning Civil Government, Second Essay An Essay Concerning Human Understanding George Berkeley The Principles of Human Knowledge David Hume An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding Volume 36 Jonathan Swift Gulliver's Travels Laurence Sterne The Life and Opinions of Tristram Shandy, Gentleman Volume 37 Henry Fielding The History of Tom Jones, a Foundling Volume 38 Charles de Secondat, Baron de Montesquieu The Spirit of the Laws Jean Jacques Rousseau A Discourse on the Origin of Inequality A Discourse on Political Economy The Social Contract Volume 39 Adam Smith An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations Volume 40 Edward Gibbon The Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire (Part 1) Volume 41 Edward Gibbon The Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire (Part 2) Volume 42 Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals Critique of Practical Reason Excerpts from The Metaphysics of Morals Preface and Introduction to the Metaphysical Elements of Ethics with a note on Conscience General Introduction to the Metaphysic of Morals The Science of Right The Critique of Judgement Volume 43 American State Papers Declaration of Independence Articles of Confederation The Constitution of the United States of America Alexander Hamilton, James Madison, John Jay The Federalist John Stuart Mill On Liberty Considerations on Representative Government Utilitarianism Volume 44 James Boswell The Life of Samuel Johnson, LL.D. Volume 45 Antoine Laurent Lavoisier Elements of Chemistry Jean Baptiste Joseph Fourier Analytical Theory of Heat Michael Faraday Experimental Researches in Electricity Volume 46 Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel The Philosophy of Right The Philosophy of History Volume 47 Johann Wolfgang von Goethe Faust Volume 48 Herman Melville Moby Dick; or, The Whale Volume 49 Charles Darwin The Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection The Descent of Man, and Selection in Relation to Sex Volume 50 Karl Marx Capital Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels Manifesto of the Communist Party Volume 51 Count Leo Tolstoy War and Peace Volume 52 Fyodor Mikhailovich Dostoevsky The Brothers Karamazov Volume 53 William James The Principles of Psychology Volume 54 Sigmund Freud The Origin and Development of Psycho-Analysis Selected Papers on Hysteria The Sexual Enlightenment of Children The Future Prospects of Psycho-Analytic Therapy Observations on "Wild" Psycho-Analysis The Interpretation of Dreams On Narcissism Instincts and Their Vicissitudes Repression The Unconscious A General Introduction to Psycho-Analysis Beyond the Pleasure Principle Group Psychology and the Analysis of the Ego The Ego and the Id Inhibitions, Symptoms, and Anxiety Thoughts for the Times on War and Death Civilization and Its Discontents New Introductory Lectures on Psycho-Analysis  
  • "GREAT THINKERS" SERIES
    13/ 12/ 2021
    The series includes 9 books by the great thinkers: 1. The Great Thinker - Adam Smith In 60 Minutes 2. The Great Thinker - Habermas In 60 Minutes 3. The Great Thinker - Hegel In 60 Minutes 4. The Great Thinker - Heidegger In 60 Minutes 5. The Great Thinker - Kant In 60 Minutes 6. The Great Thinker - Rousseau In 60 Minutes 7. The Great Thinker - Sartre In 60 Minutes 8. The Great Thinker - Nietzsche In 60 Minutes 9. The Great Thinker - Freud In 60 Minutes The author of this series is Dr. Walther Ziegler, a doctor of philosophy and a university professor. He is also the author of many philosophy books. Thanks to his seasoned experience in journalism, he succeeds in interpreting complex knowledge in an engaging and understandable way. Each of the series is about a great philosopher in the world, gathering all the thoughts of a philosopher, is presented in a mere 200 pages, you may only need 60 minutes to read it all. How good must it be to manage to be able to present such a completed and complex knowledge as a system! Walther Ziegler has given readers the core thoughts of each philosopher, along with quotes and examples to bring the philosophers' works in ways that are easy to understand, interesting, and highly topical. In the book The Great Thinker - Kant in 60 Minutes, Walther Ziegler presented Kant's works and ideas in an impressive way. Kant was interested in simple questions. How do images and perceptions come to our heads? What can we know with certainty and what not? Or as in the book The Great Thinker - Satre in 60 Minutes, where is the truth of a person? Is it fixed or found somewhere? Sartre believes that, in each person's life, we constantly discover and analyze ourselves. We are also constantly researching and analyzing the people around us, when we think of them, talk about them, write about them - whether they are alive or dead. Perhaps what determines who we are is a constant process of analysis and inquiry that we and others carry out until we die or are forgotten. It is too frivolous to identify a person by just a name, isn't it? For a first step into the realm of philosophy, you can try this series of books. The book series is available at Ex Libris Hermes, please come and pick it up!
  • A PHILOSOPHICAL MASTERPIECE "A TREATISE CONCERNING THE PRINCIPLES OF HUMAN KNOWLEDGE" BY GEORGE BERKELEY
    07/ 12/ 2021
    The philosophical work A treatise concerning the principles of human knowledge (1710) is a masterpiece by George Berkely, published at his age of 25. This treatise holds an important position in the history of empiricism in particular and of Western philosophy in general. Its central contention is the proposition that the physical world cannot exist independently of the perceiving mind, through the expression "esse est percipi" (to be is to be perceived). George Berkeley's purpose in writing this work, as he said, is "to try if I can discover what those Principles are which have introduced all that doubtfulness and uncertainty, those absurdities and contradictions, into the several sects of philosophy; insomuch that the wisest men have thought our ignorance incurable, conceiving it to arise from the natural dullness and limitation of our faculties." Translated into Vietnamese by Đinh Hồng Phúc and Mai Sơn with the revision of philosopher Bùi Văn Nam Sơn, this work was published by Tri Thức publisher in 2013. Title page of the first edition (1710) Front page of Vietnamese translation (2013) The structure of the book consists of: Introduction (including 25 subsections) and Part I (including 156 subsections). In the Introduction, Berkeley mainly criticized Locke's theory of abstract Ideas as a fundamental flawed Principle that "introduced all that Doubtfulness and Uncertainty, those Absurdities and Contradictions into the several Sects of Philosophy" (§4). For Locke and many other philosophers, the Mind "hath a power of framing abstract Ideas" (§6) by reducing  qualities or properties of individual objects to simple components to derive ones that individual objects have in common, that is, the general. Berkeley attacked this theory with a contention that abstracting such ideas is something we can't do, and the origin of that flaw is the mistaken view of language: the purpose of language is to convey our ideas, and every meaningful name represents an abstract idea. For Berkeley, language represents only general ideas, not any abstract idea. Therefore, the way we can get to the truth and avoid all mistakes is to "clear the first Principles of Knowledge, from the embarras and delusion of Words" (§25). Berkeley developed the entire content of Part I into 156 subsections in a row. Later, to help readers better understand Berkeley's presentations, the editors of Berkeley's works divided Part I into sub-categories: 1) Objects and Subjects of knowledge (§§1-2); 2) Arguments for Immaterialism (§§3-33); 3) Objections and Replies (§§34-84); and Consequences of Berkeley’ view (§§85-156). First, in the first subgroup, Berkeley identified the subjects and objects of human knowledge. The objects of knowledge are ideas, and these ideas are divided into three categories: "actually imprinted on the Senses," "perceived by attending to the Passions and Operations of the Mind," and "formed by help of Memory and Imagination." The subjects of Knowledge, according to Berkeley, are not particular persons, but "spirit," "mind," "soul," or "self." This is a dynamic perceiving entity, which is completely different from ideas, which perceives ideas, which is where ideas exist: "for the Existence of an Idea consists in being perceived." After identifying the objects and subjects of knowledge, Berkeley began to develop arguments supporting immaterialism through the next 30 subsections. Berkeley's initial argument for immaterialism is that "there is not any other Substance than Spirit" (§7). This argument was raised to refute the doctrine of abstract ideas, which argues that all perceivable objects are independent beings and completely different from those which are perceived. For Berkeley, this distinction proved unjustified because abstraction went beyond its sphere of influence. I can only abstract an object to the extent that I recognize it dependently, but I can't separate it from the spiritual perception in me of it as a self-contained entity: "all those Bodies which compose the mighty Frame of the World, have not any Subsistence without a Mind." As such, the world with only one substance is the mind, and the so-called "matter" or "substratum" of ideas cannot be regarded as substance. According to Berkeley, because things that we directly perceive all have secondary qualities and because they exist only in the mind, what we perceive is "spiritual ideas," not objects in the external world. Furthermore, on the basis of the principle of similarity, only ideas are similar to ideas, not to anything unperceivable, and he deduced that there is no similarity to ideas in the so-called material. "Any color or extensive quantity, or any perceivable property, can absolutely not exist in an unthinking subject, outside of mind," he affirmed. In this regard, Berkeley was pointing out the problem of materialism, specifically the following: One, the idea of materiality (or tangible substance) itself is a contradictory idea, in that it holds that properties that are only found in the spiritual substance can be also found in the non-spiritual body. Second, materialism is leading us to indirect realism of perception, leading to skepticism. Though ideas cannot exist on their own, they are assumed by materialists to be copies of spiritually independent beings (§15). But objects of the senses are constantly changing, while their originals are thought to be invariant, so they can't be honest copies of their originals. Third, there is no distinct meaning annexed to the concept of material substance (§17), because the concepts of substance and substratum, of what is the lift for extensive quantity, are too ambiguous and abstract that are inconceivable. Following the master argument that no object can exist outside the mind, since such objects are, in principle, impossible to perceive, Berkeley reviewed and responded to arguments that refuted the philosophy of immaterialism (subsection §34 to subsection §84). Respondence to these counterarguments is also his statements about his idealism, which is later called subjective idealism. In general, these counterarguments can be grouped into major groups: 1) of ordinary people; 2) of scientists; and 3) of religion. First of all, with arguments from ordinary people, Berkeley answered that neither did his philosophical system deny the existence of anything perceptible, nor firsthand information, - whether they existed or not did not matter, as long as they existed "in the spirit" for him; what he refuted was that materialists insist on the existence of an imperceptible substance called a "material" or "tangible substance" that supported beings with shapes, extensive quantity, motion, etc. In response to the counterarguments from the scientific side, Berkeley replied that his philosophical system was not harmful to science, if it was properly understood. It's not science's job to present metaphysical explanations, but to present the laws of operation observed in the natural world as clearly as possible. So his idealism and immaterialism are not only compatible with the right scientific practice, but they are also really useful for science to rule out the ambiguous concepts that interfere with human consciousness. Finally, there are counterarguments from the religious side. Berkeley says that although the language of the Bible refers to "materials" (e.g., mountains, rivers, vegetation, people, etc.), it does not have the same way of understanding as the materialists' one, that is, material is an imperceptible subtratrum. And since the true role of language is "marking our Conceptions, or Things only as they are known and perceived by us" (§83), his principles of presentation do not contradict the rules of language. Furthermore, the case of miracles in the Bible (Moise's scepter turned into a snake, water turned into alcohol) does not make them lose their exerted power, because it acknowledges that "the scepter turned into a snake" and "water turned into alcohol" are real. Therefore, similar to the two groups of arguments mentioned above, his immaterialism is not as dangerous as mistaken. After responding to possible counterarguments from various sides, Berkeley spent the next 49 subsections, from §85 to §134, considering the benefits his theory could bring to human cognitive activities, namely, philosophy, science, and religion. In general, the benefit that immaterialism can bring to philosophy is that it eliminates all of the "several difficult and obscure Questions, on which abundance of Speculation hath been thrown away" (§85), and once it is done, skepticism and atheism will no longer have any basis for survival, people will save much effort and time in the search of truth. In terms of science, the benefits of this theory are considered by Berkeley in the "two great provinces'' of natural science and mathematics. In the field of natural science, his aim is to counter the skeptics' contention that the true nature of things is something we cannot know in principle. The basis of this contention is the scientific interpretation of Newtonian mechanics. Berkeley's view is that in principle, we always understand the true nature of things. Scientists should not try to find the cause of impact in the natural world, because the principles of mechanics cannot help us explain the fundamental laws of nature such as attraction and cohesion of things. The principle of "analogies between events" in scientists is very susceptible to the trend of absolutization, "extending its Knowledge into general Theoremes", thus "to the prejudice of Truth" (§106). The philosophical principle of immaterialism will help scientists realize that the greatest analogy of all events is to regard the natural world as the work of a wise and benevolent agency, God, and the only correct way to interpret them is by final causes, not by corporeal causes. The last subsections of the Principles from §135 to §156, Berkeley considered spirits and God. Since Spirit is "the only supporting substance in which unthinking beings or ideas can exist" (§135), and, according to the principle of analogy, only ideas are similar to ideas, we cannot create a spiritual idea. We can only create a concept of spirit. Concepts are different from ideas in that they do not present a picture of the true content of the object being marked, but rather is the result of reflection between our ideas and those in the minds of others according to the principle of analogy. Let's just say that we don't have any idea of others' spirits, we can still infer the existence of those spirits by observing the changes in our perceptual spirits. We can derive the concept of spirit from the observation of our own self or soul, and from that, "we know other Spirits by means of our own Soul" (§140). The reason for us to do this is because of God's agency, which is present everywhere and provides a stable background on which all causal relationships take place so that we can capture the spirit of others. "He alone it is who upholding all Things by the Word of his Power, maintains that Intercourse between Spirits, whereby they are able to perceive the Existence of each other" As we can see, Berkeley's entire philosophical project was done in this work, A treatise concerning the principles of human knowledge, justifies the truths in the Gospel of God's existence as the true substance of all beings, all natural order, and the fountain of all human authentic perception. Therefore, his philosophy, namely immaterialism, has no other task than to dispel all misconceptions about God and evoke a "pious Sense of the Presence of God" for them to "reverence and embrace the salutary Truths of the Gospel" (§156).
  • GREAT BOOKS OF THE WESTERN WORLD 2
    29/ 11/ 2021
    Volume 10 Hippocrates Works Galen On the Natural Faculties Volume 11 Euclid The Thirteen Books of Euclid's Elements Archimedes On the Sphere and Cylinder Measurement of a Circle On Conoids and Spheroids On Spirals On the Equilibrium of Planes The Sand Reckoner The Quadrature of the Parabola On Floating Bodies Book of Lemmas The Method Treating of Mechanical Problems Apollonius of Perga On Conic Sections Nicomachus of Gerasa Introduction to Arithmetic Volume 12 Lucretius On the Nature of Things (translated by H.A.J. Munro) Epictetus The Discourses (translated by George Long) Marcus Aurelius The Meditations (translated by George Long) Volume 13 Virgil (translated into English verse by James Rhoades) Eclogues Georgics Aeneid Volume 14 Plutarch The Lives of the Noble Grecians and Romans (translated by John Dryden) Volume 15 P. Cornelius Tacitus (translated by Alfred John Church and William Jackson Brodribb) The Annals The Histories Volume 16 Ptolemy Almagest, (translated by R. Catesby Taliaferro) Nicolaus Copernicus On the Revolutions of Heavenly Spheres (translated by Charles Glenn Wallis) Johannes Kepler (translated by Charles Glenn Wallis) Epitome of Copernican Astronomy (Books IV–V) The Harmonies of the World (Book V) Volume 17 Plotinus The Six Enneads (translated by Stephen MacKenna and B. S. Page) Volume 18 Augustine of Hippo The Confessions The City of God On Christian Doctrine Volume 19 Thomas Aquinas Summa Theologica (First part complete, selections from second part, translated by the Fathers of the English Dominican Province and revised by Daniel J. Sullivan) Volume 20 Thomas Aquinas Summa Theologica (Selections from second and third parts and supplement, translated by the Fathers of the English Dominican Province and revised by Daniel J. Sullivan) Volume 21 Dante Alighieri Divine Comedy (Translated by Charles Eliot Norton) Volume 22 Geoffrey Chaucer Troilus and Criseyde The Canterbury Tales Volume 23 Niccolò Machiavelli The Prince Thomas Hobbes Leviathan Volume 24 François Rabelais Gargantua and Pantagruel, but only up to book 4. Volume 25 Michel Eyquem de Montaigne Essays Volume 26 William Shakespeare The First Part of King Henry the Sixth The Second Part of King Henry the Sixth The Third Part of King Henry the Sixth The Tragedy of Richard the Third The Comedy of Errors Titus Andronicus The Taming of the Shrew The Two Gentlemen of Verona Love's Labour's Lost Romeo and Juliet The Tragedy of King Richard the Second A Midsummer Night's Dream The Life and Death of King John The Merchant of Venice The First Part of King Henry the Fourth The Second Part of King Henry the Fourth Much Ado About Nothing The Life of King Henry the Fifth Julius Caesar As You Like It Volume 27 William Shakespeare Twelfth Night; or, What You Will The Tragedy of Hamlet, Prince of Denmark The Merry Wives of Windsor Troilus and Cressida All's Well That Ends Well Measure for Measure Othello, the Moor of Venice King Lear Macbeth Antony and Cleopatra Coriolanus Timon of Athens Pericles, Prince of Tyre Cymbeline The Winter's Tale The Tempest The Famous History of the Life of King Henry the Eighth Sonnets Volume 28 William Gilbert On the Loadstone and Magnetic Bodies Galileo Galilei Dialogues Concerning the Two New Sciences William Harvey On the Motion of the Heart and Blood in Animals On the Circulation of Blood On the Generation of Animals Volume 29 Miguel de Cervantes The History of Don Quixote de la Mancha (translated by John Ormsby) Volume 30 Sir Francis Bacon The Advancement of Learning Novum Organum New Atlantis Read more: GREAT BOOKS OF THE WESTERN WORLD
  • CHUYỆN ĐÔNG CHUYỆN TÂY BY AN CHI
    22/ 11/ 2021
    Chuyện Đông chuyện Tây is a collection of articles written by scholar and researcher An Chi that has been published in Today's Knowledge Journal for many years, starting in 1992. Readers have sent many difficult questions of Vietnamese language and history, science,… and hope to get answers from An Chi. Many questions are asked, for example, when the word "moong" appeared in the media, making many readers surprised because they did not understand its meaning and did not know its origin. According to An Chi, "moong" is a Vietnamese word of French origin, derived from the word "gisement", which means "bed" (mineral, soil, rock, etc.). In addition, the answers about history, culture, sports and other fields are also very thorough and interesting such as Ba Son place, the national name Đại Cồ Việt or phase "Rể Đông sàng, dâu Nam gián"… These questions were answered convincingly. Especially, he has specific examples for the answers. He also applied a lot of knowledge from Chinese, French, and English to compare and find the root of the issues, as well as find the etymology of Vietnamese. That makes his opinions more convincing and weighty. “…No one can claim to be an “encyclopedia” these days, but his answers in the magazine satisfy most readers because they are all the result of a serious research process, responsibility for science. In addition, his writing is clear, polite and intelligent, making readers pleasure…” – Prof. Cao Xuân Hạo said about An Chi. In the past, when there was no “google” for us to be able to sit down and look up everything like now, it is true that An Chi and Chuyện Đông chuyện Tây are really a valuable treasury of knowledge. The series currently has all 4 volumes at Thư Hiên, please contact Thư Hiên to get this useful knowledge.
popup

Số lượng:

Tổng tiền: